‘Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital’ reviewed by Alex Sager


Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital

Verso, London and New York, 2013. 320pp., $29.95 / £19.99 pb
ISBN 9781844679768

Reviewed by Alex Sager

About the reviewer

Alex Sager is Assistant Professor in Philosophy and University Studies at Portland State University. …

More

Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital has attracted an unusual amount of attention for an academic book on a branch of Indian social theory. Noam Chomsky, Slavoj Žižek, Robert Brenner, Archin Vanaik, and Joshua Cohen praise the book, while leading postcolonial theorists Partha Chatterjee (Chatterjee 2013) and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (Spivak 2014) have responded at length, claiming that Chibber misunderstands his interlocutors, misinterprets Marxism, and misrepresents postcolonial theory.

The book’s explicit target is the major tenets of the Indian Subaltern School represented by Ranajit Guha, Dipesh Chakrabarty, and Partha Chatterjee. However, the reason for the attention and controversy is that Subaltern Studies serves as a synecdoche for postcolonial studies as a whole. Chibber sees many postcolonial theorists as rejecting social science based on universal categories such as capitalism, class, liberalism, rationality, and objectivity and views himself as defending Marxism and the Enlightenment project against postmodern irrationalism.

Chibber’s broader agenda, along with the book’s widespread discussion in academic journals and the blogosphere, creates a number of questions for the reviewer. First, how convincing is Chibber’s rebuttal of Subaltern Studies as a theory? Second, to what extent do Chibber’s criticisms of Subaltern Studies apply to postcolonial theory more broadly? Third, are the conceptual tools and categories developed in Western social science adequate for understanding the Global South?

On Chibber’s account, Subaltern Studies defines itself in opposition to a narrative of political and economic modernization. The bourgeoisie struggled against feudalism and the monarchy, uniting workers, peasants and other groups by portraying its own interests as universal interests. It led an economic revolution to overturn feudal regulations and inaugurated a political revolution of rule of law and democratic rights. As a consequence, its power was hegemonic, commanding widespread consent, rather than merely coercive. According to this narrative, as capital spreads to other parts of the world, it will bring about similar political and economic changes, sweeping away pre-capitalist economic relations and bringing in Western political institutions of democracy, individual rights, and secularism.

Subaltern Studies rejects this narrative, contending that the colonial world is fundamentally different. The colonial bourgeoisie failed to achieve hegemony, leading to fundamental differences in power relations and in political psychology. Chibber reconstructs Subaltern Studies under six theses. First, the bourgeoisie under colonialism achieves dominance without hegemony, failing to unite the peasants and workers by representing bourgeois interests as universal interests. Instead of creating a universal political culture, it rules by coercion. Second, capitalism fails to bring about the economic and political transformations that occurred in Europe, instead leaving many feudal institutions intact. The persistence of these feudal institutions relates to the third thesis: that power in the colonial world does not map onto economic relationships, but includes pre-capitalist forms of social domination. A fourth thesis is that the failure of the bourgeoisie to include the peasants and workers leads to distinct elite and popular (subaltern) cultures whose politics is based on ethnic, communal, and/or religious interests rather than individual or class interests. Fifth, the nation-building projects of nationalist leaders incorporated European colonialism’s ideology and, by doing so, reproduced Western domination.

The final claim that the Subaltern Studies theorists make is that social theory with Western origins is Eurocentric and lacks adequate categories and tools for analyzing the colonial world. Peasant consciousness and agency are based on notions of community, religion, and honor, rather than individual interests and rationality. Furthermore, Enlightenment theories are guilty of “historicism” in which progress follows a uniform trajectory that fails to acknowledge the fragmented nature of the colonial world. These theses suggest that there are fundamental differences in capital, power, and agency between Western and non-Western societies that may require new theoretical tools.

Chibber responds to these claims by arguing that the major figures of subaltern studies misunderstand capitalism, European history, and human psychology. Subaltern Studies defines itself against a mythological version of European history. The European bourgeoisie did not usher in liberal democracy, but rather sought to limit the rights of workers and peasants, often in collaboration with the aristocracy. Political progress came in fits and starts as a result of workers struggling from below. Far from uniting into unified, homogenized nation-states, Europe remained fragmented so that precapitalist forms of domination persisted and India mirrors, rather than departs from its European counterpart.

The other theses fare no better. The best explanation for Indian leaders’ choice to modernize the economy is not ideology but the country’s participation in the world economy and the demands of citizens for a higher standard of living. Chibber also argues that humans around the world are motivated by their individual interests and that the struggle for political rights is based on universal human needs. He reanalyzes Guha and Chakrabarty’s own work and finds that peasant leaders devote substantial energy toward coalition building – something that would be unnecessary if peasants were primarily motivated by communal ties – and that peasants frequently refuse to cooperate because of individual interests. Furthermore, Subaltern Studies’ accusation of “historicism” is based on crude economic determinism in which capitalism’s success requires that all institutions be brought under its logic. Chibber shows convincingly that diversity often serves or is neutral toward the reproduction of capital. His harshest criticism is that Subaltern Studies, in its insistence on difference and fragmentation and its rejection of universal categories, replicates the essentialism and Orientalism of the European colonizers.

Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital has become a cypher for larger debates about methodology in the humanities and the social sciences, something Chibber encourages in his final chapter where he conflates Subaltern Studies with postcolonial theory (289). His reason for focusing on Subaltern Studies is because it offers influential, theoretical claims that are subject to conceptual and empirical challenge. Chibber considers a great deal of postcolonial writing to be opaque literary analysis influenced by poststructuralist theory and jargon that does not present a clear research agenda.

Chibber’s frustration with much postcolonial theory is understandable, but he is not entitled to dismiss work that he does not engage. More importantly, the opposition between postcolonial studies and the Enlightenment tradition is unfortunate. Chibber sees himself redeeming Enlightenment Universalism against postmodern postcolonialism’s irrationalism and its endorsement of relativism. But not all postcolonial thought endorses postmodernism. As Chibber points out, Marxists including Lenin, Trotsky, Luxemburg, and Gramsci extensively theorized colonialism and his insistence that Robert Young is “spectacularly mistaken” in finding continuity from Marx to Subaltern Studies is unduly dismissive.

Furthermore, not all theorists influenced by postmodernism or poststructuralism see themselves as rejecting the Enlightenment project. This was not true of Edward Said, for instance. Explanations based on material conditions are not necessarily opposed to explanations that emphasize consciousness. Hermeneutical investigations into the representation of postcolonial subjects may complement investigations into the causes and help explain the forms capital takes in different contexts around the world.

Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital is about methodology in the social sciences, opposing what Chibber sees as Marxism’s quest for “coherence and systematicity” against postcolonial studies’ eclecticism. One of the attractions of postcolonial theory is it promises to move us beyond Eurocentrism. Chibber’s claim is that this should be done not by showing differences between the East and the West, but by showing “that both parts of the globe are subject to the same basic forces and are therefore part of the same basic history.” (291) He refers to two basic forces, “the universal logic of capital” and “social agents’ universal interest in their well-being.” (291)

Though in many places Chibber clearly has the opposition between Marxism and postmodernism in mind, his basic forces can also be invoked by imperialists, advocates of modernization theory, and neoliberals. It is notable how minimal these basic forces are and how much diversity they permit. Chibber recognizes this, but does not explore how generality can be an ambiguous virtue. Until we know a great deal about the social, political, cultural, economic, and historical context of a region, it is unclear what is caused by the universal logic of capital and agents’ universal interest in their well-being. The Subaltern theorists’ question of why popular revolts in India did not lead to a national liberation movement is apt.

Chibber is surely correct that the tools of social science that have been largely developed in the Western world are adequate for understanding the Global South. No one has yet developed a compelling alternative toolset – indeed, it is unclear why hermeneutical methods favored by some postmodern postcolonialists are any less Eurocentric. Theorists should reject irrationalism, refuse to fetishize difference and diversity, strive for theoretical and stylistic clarity, and aspire to the broadest, most empirically plausible explanations. Nonetheless, theorizing about the former colonial world raises a number of questions. What is the role for economic structures and for ideas in explaining economic, political, and cultural institutions in the former colonial world? What phenomena do universal categories omit and how should they be acknowledged? Are there systemic differences between North and South rooted in history or in global economic structures? Are there similarities between former colonies that ought to be explored? Are social scientific theories and normative categories sometimes ideological (e.g., Eurocentric), imposing illegitimate assumptions and categories when they are employed in an unfamiliar context?

Postcolonial theorists, including Guha, Chakrabarty, and Chatterjee, have attempted to answer some of these questions. Chibber has shown that their answers are not compelling, but he has not demonstrated that other postcolonial theorists have not developed useful analyses for understanding the legacy of European colonialism. Nor has he offered much of a way forward.

14 October 2014

References

  • Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty 2014 Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital Cambridge Review of International Affairs vol. 27, no. 1, pp. 184–98.
  • Chatterjee, Partha 2013 Subaltern Studies and Capital Economic and Capital Weekly vol. 48, no. 37, pp. 69-75.

6 comments

  1. a fair-minded and thorough review, though in my opinion too generous. Chibber rehashes very familiar critiques of made-up caricatures of postcolonial theorists, and deliberately (in my opinion) refuses to engage with them. It’s not just Said: it’s Spivak and Derrida themselves who, far from rejecting the Enlightenment in favor of some nebulous “postmodernism” (a term which neither one of them ever writes approvingly of, and rarely writes about at all, and neither has ever accepted this term to describe themselves: the only writer who comes close to fitting that description is Baudrillard, who is about as far from postcolonial theory as it comes), seeks to understand what the Enlightenment tradition is, how it developed alongside colonialism, and how to realize what its actual ideals can be understood to be given the political context in which it developed. Spivak is an extremely sophisticated reader of Marx, and that is one reason Chibber avoids dealing with her. More to the point, Spivak and Derrida frequently read Enlightenment texts, by no means dismissing them, and Derrida often makes clear that he sees his work as in a direct line from Kant. Spivak did not call her most major book “A Critique of Postcolonial Reason” by accident, and the long and critical reading of Kant in it is deeply sympathetic to both Kant and his philosophical project. Derrida and Spivak make look obscure when you first read them, but I have to admit that after reading them for a long time, they now strike me as exceedingly clear and also rigorous, and I’ll point out that Kant and other Enlightenment figures are well-known for appearing “obscure” or unreadable especially at first. Like Ahmad’s In Theory, Chibber’s is a retrograde cheap shot, and it gets attention because reactionary thinking always does. The most shameful thing is the use of the phrase “postcolonial theory” in Chibber’s title, as at best Subaltern Studies is something like “postcolonial studies.” I don’t think Chibber has read much of postcolonial THEORY at all. Many of his bulletted summaries and so forth are so far off the mark as to belong in the New Criterion, but not a serious book of scholarship on the topic: ” postcolonial theorists as rejecting social science based on universal categories such as capitalism, class, liberalism, rationality, and objectivity and views himself as defending Marxism and the Enlightenment project against postmodern irrationalism.” that entire sentence describes a world that only exists in the minds of people who don’t (or maybe can’t) read the texts they are talking about.

  2. For someone to write a scathing critique of Chibber under a pseudonym is clearly inappropriate. I am not here to defend Chibber, but Anti-Chibber’s comments are very unrestrained and sweeping. For example, in his view, it is ‘shameful’ for Chibber to regard ‘subaltern studies’ as post-colonial theory ! At best he says,’ subaltern studies is something like postcolonial studies’, as if postcolonial studies were/are conducted without using any theory !

    The real issue that Vivek’s book poses is if historical processes in all societies follow the same course and if they can be subsumed under a universal theory. Thus theory vs history – reminiscent of the German methodenstreit – is the key question invoked by Vivek Chibber’s book and perhaps needs to be debated afresh.

  3. I’m not sure why my identity matters at all. The title of the book is “Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital.” The book spends very little time (only a few pages, if my memory is correct) discussing any of the work that is usually taught and studied as “postcolonial theory.” It does, however, make sweeping generalizations *about* postcolonial theory (and “postmodernism” and other generalities that are not closely examined) that are simply not borne out by the body of work he appears to be referencing.

    A more accurate title for Chibber’s book would have been “Subaltern Studies and the Specter of Capital.” Why he didn’t choose to title it that way I don’t know, but I can guarantee that the controversy over the book would have then been less intense and more pointed. If he wanted to talk about “postcolonial theory,” especially its engagement with Enlightenment figures and thought (including Marx), it is very odd that the book engages so little with postcolonial theory about the Enlightenment and Marx, of which there is a great deal. I am in no way suggesting Subaltern Studies is not theoretical (it certainly is); I am suggesting only that when the phrase “postcolonial theory” is used among Chibber’s likely audience (that is, the readership of Verso, his publisher), that’s not what “postcolonial theory” is taken to mean. Maybe Subaltern Studies deserves Chibber’s scathing critique; maybe it doesn’t. But that critique does not a fortiori apply to what is practically another body of work entirely, which Chibber repeatedly suggests it does (and which this review points out it does not).

    As an example: the widely-used “Colonial Discourse and Post-Colonial Theory Reader,” one of the several books to use “postcolonial theory” in the title, features 31 essays. Of those, depending on how one counts, 3 or 4 have any relation to the Subaltern Studies group Chibber examines. that book was published in 1994. readers are right to assume the writers of those 31 essays are the subject of Chibber’s book, but they aren’t. Further, the views Chibber ascribes to postcolonial theory–including his recent response to Spivak’s review–are simply not consistent with those essays, or with the larger bodies of work by their authors.

    Your statement: “the real issue that Vivek’s book poses is if historical processes in all societies follow the same course and if they can be subsumed under a universal theory,” is one of the main issues that, on my reading, postcolonial theory focuses, Spivak in particular, using Marx in particular, of whom it is fair to say she is a leading (if, certainly, unorthodox) scholar. She absolutely does not dismiss the “universal applicability” of many key Marxist concepts like class, alienation, labor, and. That is also not to say that she accepts that calling them “universal” simply ends the story about them, either. On my reading, this “issue” is one of the main things postcolonial theory is about and has been about from the beginning, and suggesting it needs to be torn apart for failing to address that issue is galling, and that fact that Chibber essentially repeats what right-wing critics of people like Spivak have been lobbing at her and others for decades, but in Marxist clothing (and this not for the first time either), is galling as well.

    Look at the 6 “arguments associated with the Subalterns do in fact resonate with much of the larger field” Chibber supplies in his extremely dismissive response to Spivak. These don’t define postcolonial theory at all. They are caricatures. In so far as they can be understood specifically and not vaguely (but they are worded extremely vaguely), at best they point to the very questions with which postcolonial theory has been engaged from its inception, questions which postcolonial theory simply does not answer the way Chibber says it does: “A boilerplate scepticism towards universalizing discourse, and hence towards many of the theories emanating from the Enlightenment tradition” is something only someone who has not read Spivak’s Critique of Postcolonial Reason could possibly say. That book is ABOUT Kant and Marx, both of whose theories Spivak takes very seriously, *believes in and endorses* in many ways, and not at all with “boilerplate skepticism.”

  4. What’s in a name ! I’ll refrain from saying anything more on the awkward pseudonym.

    There are a large number of intellectuals, and not only the five big names mentioned by Alex Sager, who are sympathetic to Chibber’s standpoint. The standpoint is that societies based on or sucked into capitalist production require Marxian categories to understand and change them. Chibber believes that attempts have been made to dilute or compromise Marxian categories in subaltern studies under the influence of various postisms. Therefore, he is in his own way trying to defend the universal validity of Marxian theory, which for him is the continuation of the Enlightenment worldview committe to reason, science and progress.

    Surely, views can differ on how well Chibber has criticised subaltern theory or defended his Marxism.

  5. Marx is the logical offshoot of liberalism and capitalism, as Moroccan historian Abdelah Laroui suggests. His class model does society more good (by unifying it and minimizing divisons) than postcolonialists and postmodenists who excel at creating infinite identity categories that tribalize, retribalize and fragment civic society. After all, unity and uniformity is a fundmental principle of the natural world and by extension the social world. Only the anthropological and ethnographic theories that feed on postmodern thought deviate from that universal rule and take pleasure at reifiying differences of societies and fail to see what unifies people across the primitive divisons of kin, tribe, and race. As a postcolonial subject, I can’t see why my condition and my history is in any way different from the Western condition and history. We all seem to roughly follow the same historical course. The ambivalence of the postcolonial critics is that, in theory, they are the most diehard opponents of modernity and, in practice, are the beneficiaries of its incredible inventions.

Leave a Reply to sarban Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *